笔下文学
会员中心 我的书架

CHAPTER V

(快捷键←)[上一章]  [回目录]  [下一章](快捷键→)

the tribunate

when an exact proportion cannot be established between the constituent parts of the state, or when causes that cannot be removed continually alter the relation of one part to another, recourse is had to the institution of a peculiar magistracy that enters into no corporate unity with the rest. this restores to each term its right relation to the others, and provides a link or middle term between either prince and people, or prince and sovereign, or, if necessary, both at once.

this body, which i shall call the tribunate, is the preserver of the laws and of the legislative power. it serves sometimes to protect the sovereign against the government, as the tribunes of the people did at rome; sometimes to uphold the government against the people, as the council of ten now does at venice; and sometimes to maintain the balance between the two, as the ephors did at sparta.

the tribunate is not a constituent part of the city, and should have no share in either legislative or executive power; but this very fact makes its own power the greater: for, while it can do nothing, it can prevent anything from being done. it is more sacred and more revered, as the defender of the laws, than the prince who executes them, or than the sovereign which ordains them. this was seen very clearly at rome, when the proud patricians, for all their scorn of the people, were forced to bow before one of its officers, who had neither auspices nor jurisdiction.

the tribunate, wisely tempered, is the strongest support a good constitution can have; but if its strength is ever so little excessive, it upsets the whole state. weakness, on the other hand, is not natural to it: provided it is something, it is never less than it should be.

it degenerates into tyranny when it usurps the executive power, which it should confine itself to restraining, and when it tries to dispense with the laws, which it should confine itself to protecting. the immense power of the ephors, harmless as long as sparta preserved its morality, hastened corruption when once it had begun. the blood of agis, slaughtered by these tyrants, was avenged by his successor; the crime and the punishment of the ephors alike hastened the destruction of the republic, and after cleomenes sparta ceased to be of any account. rome perished in the same way: the excessive power of the tribunes, which they had usurped by degrees, finally served, with the help of laws made to secure liberty, as a safeguard for the emperors who destroyed it. as for the venetian council of ten, it is a tribunal of blood, an object of horror to patricians and people alike; and, so far from giving a lofty protection to the laws, it does nothing, now they have become degraded, but strike in the darkness blows of which no one dare take note.

the tribunate, like the government, grows weak as the number of its members increases. when the tribunes of the roman people, who first numbered only two, and then five, wished to double that number, the senate let them do so, in the confidence that it could use one to check another, as indeed it afterwards freely did.

the best method of preventing usurpations by so formidable a body, though no government has yet made use of it, would be not to make it permanent, but to regulate the periods during which it should remain in abeyance. these intervals, which should not be long enough to give abuses time to grow strong, may be so fixed by law that they can easily be shortened at need by extraordinary commissions.

this method seems to me to have no disadvantages, because, as i have said, the tribunate, which forms no part of the constitution, can be removed without the constitution being affected. it seems to be also efficacious, because a newly restored magistrate starts not with the power his predecessor exercised, but with that which the law allows him.

先看到这(加入书签) | 推荐本书 | 打开书架 | 返回首页 | 返回书页 | 错误报告 | 返回顶部