笔下文学
会员中心 我的书架

CHAPTER XXIV. THE MEASURE OF PUNISHMENTS.

(快捷键←)[上一章]  [回目录]  [下一章](快捷键→)

we have seen that the true measure of crimes is the injury done to society. this is one of those palpable truths which, however little dependent on quadrants or telescopes for their discovery, and fully within the reach of any ordinary intelligence, are yet, by a marvellous combination of circumstances, only recognised clearly and firmly by some few thinkers, belonging to every nationality and to every age. but asiatic ideas, and passions clothed with authority and power, have, generally by imperceptible movements, sometimes by violent assaults on the timid credulity of mankind, dissipated those simple notions, which perhaps formed the first philosophy of primitive communities, and to which the enlightenment of this age seems likely to reconduct us, but to do so with that greater sureness, which can be gained from an exact[200] investigation into things, from a thousand unhappy experiences, and from the very obstacles that militate against it.

they who have thought that the criminal’s intention was the true measure of crimes were in the wrong. for the intention depends on the actual impression of things upon a man, and on his precedent mental disposition, things which vary in all men and in each man, according to the very rapid succession of his ideas, his passions, and his circumstances. it would, therefore, be necessary to form not only a particular code for each citizen, but a fresh law for every crime. sometimes with the best intentions men do the greatest evil to society; and sometimes with the very worst they do it the greatest good.

others again measure crimes rather by the rank of the person injured than by their importance in regard to the public weal. were this the true measure of crimes, any act of irreverence towards the supreme being should be punished more severely than the assassination of a monarch, whereas the superiority of his nature affords an infinite compensation for the difference of the offence.

lastly, some have thought that the gravity of an act’s sinfulness should be an element in the measure of crimes. but an impartial observer of the true relations between man and man, and between man[201] and god, will easily perceive the fallacy of this opinion. for the former relationship is one of equality; necessity alone, from the clash of passions and opposing interests, having given rise to the idea of the public utility, the basis of human justice. but the other relationship is one of dependence on a perfect being and creator, who has reserved to himself alone the right of being at the same time legislator and judge, and can alone unite the two functions without bad effects. if he has decreed eternal punishments to those who disobey his omnipotence, what insect shall dare to take the place of divine justice, or shall wish to avenge that being, who is all-sufficient to himself, who can receive from things no impression of pleasure nor of pain, and who alone of all beings acts without reaction? the degree of sinfulness in an action depends on the unsearchable wickedness of the heart, which cannot be known by finite beings without a revelation. how, then, found thereon a standard for the punishment of crimes? in such a case men might punish when god pardons, and pardon when god punishes. if men can act contrary to the almighty by offending him, they may also do so in the punishments they inflict.

先看到这(加入书签) | 推荐本书 | 打开书架 | 返回首页 | 返回书页 | 错误报告 | 返回顶部